[D66] After Finitude: speculative materialism, contingency and hyper-chaos

Antid Oto protocosmos66 at gmail.com
Fri Dec 30 10:38:21 CET 2011


Filosofie leesvoer, een van de ontdekkingen van 2011 alhoewel al verschenen in
2008. Wat me interesseert is of dialectical materialism of Badiou's materialist
dialectics verenigbaar danwel onverenigbaar is met de hyper-chaos van
Meillassoux. Over chaos gesproken: Ik was in tijdje geleden in de London Review
Bookshop in londen, en trok een willekeurig boek uit het rekje wetenschap. Het
boek bleek Chaos van James Gleick te zijn. Chaos in actie! :) Ook
aanbevelenswaardig naast zijn recent verschenen boek "The Information".



After Finitude

Philosophy has always arisen as a response to big, burdening metaphysical
questions like “where do we come from?” and “why do we exist?” Quentin
Meillassoux, in his brief but profound book recently translated from the French
by Ray Brassier, After Finitude, confidently surveys the trajectory of
contemporary philosophy in meeting these obstacles and uncovers a remarkable
consequence that it has entailed; viz., the resurgence of irrational religiosity.

The philosophy of finitude, represented by postmodernity, maintains that our
finite experience of life is the ultimate horizon of human knowledge. There is
no absolute truth, thinking the absolute is pretentious. We have no grounds for
claiming that a determinate reality—whether it is this God, this society, or
this ideology—must necessarily exist the way it is. The recognition that we are
finite and limited beings thrown into a particular time and place discredits all
discourses that claim access to ultimate truth.

More to the point, radical finitude owes its strength to what Meillassoux calls
“correlationism”. Correlationism, in a word, proscribes any knowledge of the
absolute. Whereas pre-critical naïve realism took it for granted that objects
appeared to subjects as they actually were, the basic line of argument for
correlationism is that objects are relative to the subjects perceiving them. We
have no access to things-in-themselves so all knowledge is conditioned by our
finite apprehension of sensible qualities.

This umbilical link between objects and subjects is all that remains. In a
sense, correlationism absolutizes the correlation itself.

But if objects are unthinkable apart from how they appear to us, then it seems
unjustifiable to assert that something, rather than absolute nothingness,
subsists beyond our representations. Contemporary philosophy is utterly agnostic
on this point.

For Meillassoux, it is clear that correlationism “culminates in the
disappearance of the pretension to think any absolutes, but not in the
disappearance of absolutes.” In other words, contemporary philosophy has exposed
the inherent limits of thought and has left a deficient gap of knowledge in its
wake. Metaphysical problems like “why is there something rather than nothing?”
still occur, but philosophers now admit no solution.

The unforeseen upshot Meillassoux catches sight of in this skeptical position is
a shocking return to superstition. Reason cannot answer why what is, is the way
it is, so religious belief systems, including the most alarming ones, have
served to posit some supreme meaning underlying all things. In perhaps his
strongest chapter, “Metaphysics, Fideism, Speculation”, Meillassoux demonstrates
how “correlationism itself does not maintain any irrational position” but is
incapable of disqualifying “irrational discourses about the absolute on the
pretext of their irrationality.” Radical finitude can only think the limits of
thought; “it makes no positive pronouncements whatsoever about the absolute.”

In trying to prevent any claims regarding the absolute, the critique of
metaphysics has paradoxically fueled fanaticism and a form of ultimate truth
that only fideistic piety can provide.

What seems obvious to Meillassoux, however, is that philosophy could have gone
in another direction other than correlationism. The great Galilean-Copernican
revolution discovered for the first time thought’s capacity to gain knowledge of
the world independently of thought’s relation with it. Moreover, the very
inception of empirical science replaced myths and fabulations with repeatable
experiments that could test and rationally support one theory over another
concerning a world unaffected by human existence or inexistence.

In the simplest possible terms: modern science indicated the autonomy of an
object without recourse to a subject’s correlation with it.

Nevertheless, instead of reorienting itself in an attempt to think the
revolutionary potential of science, modern philosophy carried out its own
“counter-revolution”—chiefly with the transcendental idealism of Kant and
Berkley—which asserted that the subject was still central to the process of
knowledge; viz., correlationism.

But, conceding the stability and apparent permanence of nature’s physical laws
that can be empirically studied, it is still plausible that given the same
initial conditions “a hundred different events” could have resulted. While
majority opinion objects that this universe could not possibly have occurred by
erratic chance, scientific discourse knows that “the acausal universe is just as
consistent and just as capable of accounting for our actual experience as the
causal universe”. The crucial difference between the two hypotheses, however, is
that an acausal universe is devoid of enigmas in need of superfluous explanation.

If, then, an extreme form of incalculable chaos underlies every aspect of
empirical constancy it stands to reason that chaos itself, rather than God or
even the visible world, is the only determinate absolute.

Meillassoux identifies the exigent task of philosophy today as overcoming the
current deadlock between ideological dogmatism and skeptical fanaticism. He
thinks that if the great schism dividing science and philosophy is resolved it
may succeed “in waking us from our correlationist slumber.”

The task Meillassoux sets for himself in his unique model of “Speculative
Materialism” involves some way of thinking a non-metaphysical and non-religious
absolute without regressing to either naïve realism or correlationism; neither
of which are viable nor desirable to resuscitate.

Meillassoux proffers that scientific knowledge of reality insists that there is
no ultimate Reason governing the world. Everything springs forth from an
omnipotent “hyper-Chaos.” But unlike relativist postmodernism, this speculative
thesis is a “positive knowledge” without any marks of finite and limited
knowledge. There is no other meaning capable of expanding our understanding of
existence; especially not an inappropriate religious one.

To be clear, Meillassoux takes metaphysical problems to be genuine ones. “Why is
the world thus and not otherwise?” is an excellent question and Meillassoux’s
remarkable reply is “for no reason!” There really are answers. There are no
mysteries after all.

It is worth asking, on the other hand, whether Meillassoux’s speculative
thinking could coincide with a return to a non-anthropological metaphysics
rather than abandoning it altogether. As other speculative realists have found,
sometimes where the danger grows is also where the solution hides. This would,
at least, curtail the ethico-political wilderness that Meillassoux is ostensibly
journeying towards.

One thing is for sure, Meillassoux will wake up comatose metaphysicians and
fundamentalists alike.

http://indecentbazaar.wordpress.com/2011/01/19/thought-honors-itself-by-defending-what-is-damned-as-nihilism/

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Quentin_Meillassoux


More information about the D66 mailing list